Monday, December 9, 2013
Marder on Plants
Marder thinks that plants should have the right to flourish and the right to be free of arbitrary violence. The basis for these rights is plant subjectivity or agency. In other words, plants have a basic ability to actively shape their environments. As such, they should have certain rights. Plant intelligence studies seem to undermine Singer's justification of vegetarianism because it shows that just because someone avoids eating animals does not yet mean that one is eating ethically. Plants, as something with their own kind of subjectivity, seem to be just as deserving of rights as animals are. Just because they have rights does not entail that they also have responsibilities. We might have obligations to plants even if plants are not the kind of thing to have their own obligations. It may even turn out that all eating is unethical. If this is the case, then this is not to say that we should stop all eating. Rather, the question of whether we should eat is akin to the question of whether we should exist. Marder says that the easiest rule for respectful eating is to remember that the sources of our food are not just calories for human consumption. There is some sort of 'good' for that plant (or animal) itself.
Monday, December 2, 2013
Korsgaard on the Origin of 'the Good'
Korsgaard distinguishes between two ways that we use the
word 'good'. First, there is the
everyday 'evaluative' sense of the word.
For example, when we call something a good book, a good car, a good pair
of shoes, a good cup of coffee, etc. In
the evaluative sense, a thing is good according to our goals. There is also the 'final' sense of good,
i.e., 'the good'. This sense of the word
means something like the final aim or total goodness for a thing. This is often thought to be something that is
good for it's own sake (good in itself).
In this paper, Korsgaard is concerned with the nature of 'the good'.
She then contrasts three theories about the final
good. Intrinsic good theory is the
theory that goodness is a real property of an object. For example, an action is morally good as a
matter of fact in the same way that my new shoes are red. Hedonism is the theory that the final good is
what makes us happy. Eudaimonism is the
theory that the final good is to function well or to have one's own biological
organism in a state of well-being.
Korsgaard argues that the benefit of a eudaimonistic theory is that it
can explain the relationship between evaluative good and final good. In order to explain this, she introduces the
extended-evaluative sense of the word.
To be good in the extended-evaluative sense means to be good for some
purpose and also be be functioning healthily.
In this sense, to have a final good just means to be aware of oneself as
being in good condition. In other words,
having a final good means being able to take an evaluative approach to one's
own life. As such, the final good
requires some level of reflexivity. In
other words, to have a final good, one must be aware of one's final good. It seems that rational consciousness either
introduces another kind of final good or it is a more complex awareness of
one's own final good. Either way, having
a final good requires reflexivity.
Korsgaard on Fellow Creatures
In this essay, Korsgaard begins by noting the unstable
attitudes that we have towards animals.
On the one hand, we seem to agree that it is wrong to inflict pain on an
animal or to kill an animal without good reason. On the other hand, it seems like any reason
other than mere enjoyment is a good reason to harm or kill an animal. Korsgaard notes that generally, those who
want to argue for better treatment of animals will often emphasize the
similarities between humans and non-humans whereas those who want to defend the
status quo will emphasize the difference between humans and non-humans. Korsgaard will follow neither of these
tactics. Instead, she thinks that there
is a big difference between humans and non-humans and that it is because of
this difference that we ought to treat animals better.
What is the difference between humans and non-human
animals? Humans have a capacity for
reflective self-awareness. We don't
merely act on instinct--we think about our actions and have the capacity to
choose to act other than our instincts drive us. Although Korsgaard seems to be open to the
possibility that some non-humans have a rudimentary level of self-awareness,
humans seem to be rationally and reflexively aware of their own consciousness
in a way that other animals are not.
Hume seems to think that this difference means that we have no obligations
to animals whatsoever. Kant thinks that
although we have no obligations to animals, we should treat animals well as a
duty to ourselves and other rational beings.
In short, Kant thinks that to ignore the suffering of animals is to dull
our capacity for sympathy and empathy.
To treat animals well is a sort of practice to treat humans well. Because animals are analagous to humans in
some ways, we should treat animals well in order to keep up our capacity to
care about other people.
Korsgaard on Agency
In this article, Korsgaard is concerned with agency. Agency is the ability to perform
actions. Someone who can perform actions
is an agent. Korsgaard describes two different
kinds of theories about agency: the normative account and the natural
account. On the natural account, an
action is just what happens when there is a causal relationship between a
belief and a behavior. This is a purely
descriptive account. The normative
account of agency is not purely descriptive.
On the normative account, an action only happens if the agent's beliefs
and actions are organized in a certain way.
For example, Plato's account of agency includes the theory that an
action is performed only if one's rational capacity is in control of the other
parts of the person (spirit and appetite).
Kant's account of agency includes the theory that an action is performed
only when an agent reflectively considers the axiom that is guiding his action
and then proceeds only if the axiom can be made universal law. Korsgaard thinks that any natural account of
agency must also be supplemented with a normative account because only a
normative account of agency can explain two implications that arise when we
attribute agency.
When we attribute agency to someone, Korsgaard says there
are two resulting implications. First,
it seems like an action is somehow expressive of who a person is and the agent
has some kind of ownership over his or her actions. She calls this the identity implication. In other words, actions express the identity
of a person. Second, actions can fail in
a way that simple causal linkages cannot.
For example, the action of dodging a ball has a goal of avoiding being
hit by a ball. Even if I move my body in
response to a belief or desire, my action has failed if my goal has not been
met. Korsgaard calls this the activity
implication. Only a normative account of
agency can help to explain these two implications.
Diamond on Eating People
Diamond, like Singer and Regan, wants to argue for
vegetarianism. She notes that the
arguments of Singer and Regan focus on the interests and capacities of
individual animals as a basis for why we should not eat meat. For Singer, eating meat is wrong because it
contributes to the pain of animals. For
Regan, it is this capacity to experience pain that is the basis of animal
rights. Diamond says that such arguments
are failing to recognize the significant issue.
Such arguments usually rely on some sort of analogy between animals and
non-rational human beings. E.g., because
animals and non-rational humans are both capable of experiencing pain, it is
wrong to eat both animals and non-rational humans. This is not the relevant analogy, Diamond
says.
The proper analogy is not to talk about eating animals and
people but to talk about the death rituals for animals and people. Diamond says that the reason why we don't eat
dead people is because humans are not the kind of thing to be eaten. Our concept of what counts as a kind of thing
to be eaten changes over time. We tend
not to eat or treat badly entities that we consider to be 'fellow
creatures'. Humans, Diamond says, are the
kind of things that we honor in death with ceremony; they are also the kind of
things to be named rather than numbered.
Clearly there are many examples where humans have numbered other humans
or where humans have been disrespectful towards other humans in life and in
death. Again, the notion about who we
count as a 'fellow' creature or 'fellow' human changes over time. Diamond says that we should extend the notion
of fellow creature to non-human animals.
Regan on Animal Rights
Like Singer, Regan wants to
provide an argument for vegetarianism.
Unlike Singer, Regan does not want to base his argument on
utilitarianism. Instead, Regan thinks
that animal rights are the way to defend vegetarianism. We can think of rights in three ways. A legal right is a right granted by a legal authority. A natural right is what people talk about when
they think that there is a naturally given right that people (or animals) ought
to have. A moral right is just the other side of a
moral obligation or duty. If someone has
a duty to do X for you, then you have a right to have them do X. Regan is concerned with rights of the second
and third kind. Regean claims that Singer's
strongest arguments in favor of vegetarianism are arguments based on animals
rights. Specifically, it seems that
animals have a right to life.
Why might we think that animals have a right to life? Regan thinks that although Singer is wrong to
base his arguments in utilitarianism, there is something right about focusing
on an animal's capacity for pain. Regan
says that the capacity for suffering is the basis of a right to life, or a
right to live. He notes even though some humans are non-rational, they
still have similar capacities for suffering as non-human animals. Regan says that the reasons why we don't eat
non-rational human beings apply to animals as well. Namely, we don't eat non-rational human
beings because they have the capacity to suffer. This capacity to suffer is the basis of a
right to life. Regan notes that a
rights-based approach is better equipped to explain why we do not kill and eat
non-rational humans better than utilitarianism, Kantian ethics and egoism
(self-interest).
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)